Integration and Implementation Insights

Integration and Implementation Insights

A community blog and repository of resources for improving research impact on complex real-world problems

A guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for interdisciplinary researchers

By Katie Moon and Deborah Blackman

katie-moon

How can understanding philosophy improve our research? How can an understanding of what frames our research influence our choices? Do researchers’ personal thoughts and beliefs shape research design, outcomes and interpretation?

These questions are all important for social science research. Here we present a philosophical guide for scientists to assist in the production of effective social science (adapted from Moon and Blackman, 2014).

deborah-blackman

Understanding philosophy is important because social science research can only be meaningfully interpreted when there is clarity about the decisions that were taken that affect the research outcomes. Some of these decisions are based, not always knowingly, on some key philosophical principles, as outlined in the figure below.

Philosophy provides the general principles of theoretical thinking, a method of cognition, perspective and self-awareness, all of which are used to obtain knowledge of reality and to design, conduct, analyse and interpret research and its outcomes. The figure below shows three main branches of philosophy that are important in the sciences and serves to illustrate the differences between them.

guide-to-ontology-moon

(Source: Moon and Blackman 2014)

The first branch is ontology, or the ‘study of being’, which is concerned with what actually exists in the world about which humans can acquire knowledge. Ontology helps researchers recognize how certain they can be about the nature and existence of objects they are researching. For instance, what ‘truth claims’ can a researcher make about reality? Who decides the legitimacy of what is ‘real’? How do researchers deal with different and conflicting ideas of reality?

To illustrate, realist ontology relates to the existence of one single reality which can be studied, understood and experienced as a ‘truth’; a real world exists independent of human experience. Meanwhile, relativist ontology is based on the philosophy that reality is constructed within the human mind, such that no one ‘true’ reality exists. Instead, reality is ‘relative’ according to how individuals experience it at any given time and place.

Epistemology

The second branch is epistemology, the ‘study of knowledge’. Epistemology is concerned with all aspects of the validity, scope and methods of acquiring knowledge, such as a) what constitutes a knowledge claim; b) how can knowledge be acquired or produced; and c) how the extent of its transferability can be assessed. Epistemology is important because it influences how researchers frame their research in their attempts to discover knowledge.

By looking at the relationship between a subject and an object we can explore the idea of epistemology and how it influences research design. Objectivist epistemology assumes that reality exists outside, or independently, of the individual mind. Objectivist research is useful in providing reliability (consistency of results obtained) and external validity (applicability of the results to other contexts).

Constructionist epistemology rejects the idea that objective ‘truth’ exists and is waiting to be discovered. Instead, ‘truth’, or meaning, arises in and out of our engagement with the realities in our world. That is, a ‘real world’ does not preexist independently of human activity or symbolic language. The value of constructionist research is in generating contextual understandings of a defined topic or problem.

Subjectivist epistemology relates to the idea that reality can be expressed in a range of symbol and language systems, and is stretched and shaped to fit the purposes of individuals such that people impose meaning on the world and interpret it in a way that makes sense to them. For example, a scuba diver might interpret a shadow in the water according to whether they were alerted to a shark in the area (the shark), waiting for a boat (the boat), or expecting a change in the weather (clouds). The value of subjectivist research is in revealing how an individual’s experience shapes their perception of the world.

Philosophical perspectives

Stemming from ontology (what exists for people to know about) and epistemology (how knowledge is created and what is possible to know) are philosophical perspectives, a system of generalized views of the world, which form beliefs that guide action.

Philosophical perspectives are important because, when made explicit, they reveal the assumptions that researchers are making about their research, leading to choices that are applied to the purpose, design, methodology and methods of the research, as well as to data analysis and interpretation. At the most basic level, the mere choice of what to study in the sciences imposes values on one’s subject.

Understanding the philosophical basis of science is critical in ensuring that research outcomes are appropriately and meaningfully interpreted. With an increase in interdisciplinary research, an examination of the points of difference and intersection between the philosophical approaches can generate critical reflection and debate about what we can know, what we can learn and how this knowledge can affect the conduct of science and the consequent decisions and actions.

How does your philosophical standpoint affect your research? What are your experiences of clashing philosophical perspectives in interdisciplinary research? How did you become aware of them and resolve them? Do you think that researchers need to recognize different philosophies in interdisciplinary research teams?

To find out more : Moon, K., and Blackman, D. (2014). A Guide to Understanding Social Science Research for Natural Scientists. Conservation Biology , 28 : 1167-1177. Online:  http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/cobi.12326/full

Biography: Katie Moon is a Post Doctoral Research Fellow at the University of New South Wales, Canberra. She is also an adjunct at the Institute for Applied Ecology at the University of Canberra. She has worked in the environmental policy arena for 17 years within Australia and Europe, in government, the private sector and academia. Her research focuses on how the right policy instruments can be paired to the right people; the role of evidence in policy development and implementation; and how to increase policy implementation success .

Biography: Deborah Blackman is a Professor in Public Sector Management Strategy and Deputy Director of the Public Service Research Group at the University of New South Wales, Canberra. She researches knowledge transfer in a range of applied, real world contexts. The common theme of her work is creating new organisational conversations in order to improve organisational effectiveness. This has included strengthening the performance management framework in the Australian Public Service; the role of social capital in long-term disaster recovery; and developing a new diagnostic model to support effective joined-up working in whole of government initiatives .

Related posts:

A guide for interdisciplinary researchers: Adding axiology alongside ontology and epistemology by Peter Deane https://i2insights.org/2018/05/22/axiology-and-interdisciplinarity/

Epistemological obstacles to interdisciplinary research by Evelyn Brister https://i2insights.org/2017/10/31/epistemology-and-interdisciplinarity/

Transforming transdisciplinarity: Interweaving the philosophical with the pragmatic to move beyond either/or thinking by Katie Ross and Cynthia Mitchell https://i2insights.org/2018/11/13/transdisciplinarity-and-either-or-thinking/

What is the role of theory in transdisciplinary research? by Workshop Group on Theory at 2015 Basel International Transdisciplinary Conference http://i2insights.org/2016/02/17/role-of-theory-in-transdisciplinary-research/

Share this:

13 thoughts on “a guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for interdisciplinary researchers”.

Hi Katie and Deborah, First of all want to thank you for such incredible synthesis! Then I want to ask you, how can we situate a paradigm or an school or though in this map? For example, where do you think we can situate the complex paradigm of Edgar Morin? in between the relativistic ontology? or critical theory? thanks in advance.

  • Pingback: creative drift: on being natural - bob's thoughts, images, feelings

The table summary is admirable. All your write is very nice

  • Pingback: A guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for interdisciplinary researchers | Learning Research Methods
  • Pingback: Week 2 – Ontology and Epistemology – Research Methods

Great post! I really like the table and find it a very helpful illustration!

Hi Kate, thank you very much for helping out. I understand the subject matter more now than before Olushola

  • Pingback: RES 701, Week 2, Ontology & Epistemology – RES701 Research Methods

Thanks so much for the debate and discussion around the blog post. Machiel is right in pointing out that the blog post (and the article it is based on) was intended as a conversation piece, and we’re pleased that a useful conversation is taking place. The resources and links are very helpful, philosophy is a fascinating discipline and the opportunity to learn and expand our thinking is endless.

We tried to make it clear in the article the blog post is based on that we wanted to bring attention to philosophy; it was obviously impossible to do the discipline of philosophy any real justice within 6,000 words. We wanted to start a conversation: “The purpose of the guide is to open the door to social science research and thus demonstrate that scientists can bring different and legitimate principles, assumptions, and interpretations to their research.”

As Jessica and Melissa point out, it can be challenging to offer social research to a natural science community that typically adopts a narrow philosophical position (e.g. objectivist). The paper was intended to encourage natural scientists to consider alternative ways of generating knowledge, particularly about the human, as opposed to natural, world.

We accept unequivocally that the framework does not get close to accommodating the depth and diversity of philosophy. Adam, we agree that the approach we have taken may not resonate with some philosophers, but we wanted to communicate with a particular audience (conservation scientists) and so we defined ontologies and epistemologies (and posited them relative to one another) that are most commonly observed within this discipline and that might be best understood by the audience. We tried to identify points of difference between ontologies, epistemologies and philosophical perspectives in an attempt to explain how they can influence research design. In the article, we use a case of deforestation in rainforests to demonstrate how different positions can influence the nature of the research questions and outcomes, including the assumptions that will be made.

We did explain in the introduction to our paper the limitations of our approach: “The multifaceted nature and interpretation of each of the concepts we present in our guide means they can be combined in a diversity of ways (see also Lincoln & Guba 2000; Schwandt 2000; Evely et al. 2008; H¨oijer 2008; Cunliffe 2011; Tang 2011). Therefore, our guide represents just one example of how the elements (i.e., different positions within the main branches of philosophy) of social research can apply specifically to conservation science. We recognize that by distilling and defining the elements in a simplified way we have necessarily constrained argument and debate surrounding each element. Furthermore, the guide had to have some structure. In forming this structure, we do not suggest that researchers must consider first their ontological and then their epistemological position and so on; they may well begin by exploring their philosophical perspective.”

This point comes back to Bruce’s comment, about pragmatic approaches to research. Often researchers pick and choose between a range of options that will allow them to define and answer their research questions in a way that makes most sense to them. We make this point in the paper: “Each perspective is characterized by an often wide ranging pluralism, which reflects the complex evolution of philosophy and the varied contributions of philosophers through time (Crotty 1998). All ontologies, epistemologies, and philosophical perspectives are characterized by this pluralism, including the prevailing (post) positivist approach of the natural sciences. It is common for more than one philosophical perspective to resonate with researchers and for researchers to change their perspective (and thus epistemological and ontological positions) toward their research over time (Moses & Knutsen 2012). Thus, scientists do not necessarily commit to one philosophical perspective and all associated characteristics (Bietsa 2010).”

We tried to anticipate concerns that scholars of philosophy might have with our rather reductionist approach, but felt that the more important contribution to make was to bring attention to alternative worldviews, and highlight the importance of philosophy in generating any type of knowledge.

With respect to the characterization of epistemologies, we adopted a continuum provided by Crotty (1998) that focuses on the relationship between the subject and the object. Again, this choice was made on the basis of our audience, to demonstrate that different types of relationship can exist between subject and object

This blog post has generated an interesting discussion on the Association for Interdisciplinary Studies listserv ([email protected]). Selected excerpts below.

Adam Potthast: I hate to make one of my first posts to this list critical without the time to correct some of the errors, but I don’t think you’d see many philosophers agreeing with the characterizations of philosophical views in this post. The infographic strongly mischaracterizes a lot of these positions, and the section on epistemology doesn’t map on to any of the standard understandings of epistemology in the discipline of philosophy. I’d caution against thinking of it as a reliable source to the philosophy behind science.

Gabriele Bammer: Thanks Adam for raising the alarm. It would be great if you and/or others who have problems with this post would spell out your criticisms – not only via this listserv, but (more importantly from my perspective) in a comment on the blog itself. Non-philosophers are hungry for a version of epistemology, ontology etc that they can understand and use and this blog post (and the paper it is based on) address this need. If it is seriously misleading though, that’s obviously a problem. It’s important that this is pointed out and that better alternatives are offered. I appreciate that time is an issue for everyone – anything you can do will be appreciated.

Stuart Henry: Well a good start, so we don’t reinvent the wheel again is James Welch’s article: https://oakland.edu/Assets/upload/docs/AIS/Issues-in-Interdisciplinary-Studies/2009-Volume-27/05_Vol_27_pp_35_69_Interdisciplinarity_and_the_History_of_Western_Epistemology_(James_Welch_IV) .pdf

Gabriele Bammer: Thanks Stuart, I may be missing something, but it seems to me that Welch’s article covers different terrain, being more about the philosophy underpinning interdisciplinarity. What Moon and Blackman provide is a quick guide to understanding people’s different philosophical positions, so that if you are working in a team, for example, you can better understand why someone sees the world differently. The Toolbox developed by Eigenbrode, O’Rourke and others provides a practical way of uncovering these differences.

Julie Thompson Klein: Good point Gabriele about the value of the Toolbox, though people still need the kind of background you’re aiming to provide.

Machiel Keestra: Although I agree that the blog post should perhaps not so much be taken to offer a current representation of the main positions in philosophy of science or about the interconnections between epistemological and ontological positions, I think it does a nice job in offering a conversation piece: what are relevant positions and options that people might -implicitly– take and how are they different from other positions. Given the modest ambitions of the authors, I think that is a fair result.

In addition to the interesting approach offered by the Toolbox Project, an alternative is presented in Jan Schmidt’s Towards a philosophy of interdisciplinarity: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs10202-007-0037-8 In our Introduction to interdisciplinary research, I’ve inserted an all-too brief philosophy of science which should help to raise some understanding of this difficult issue as well: https://www.academia.edu/22420234/An_Introduction_to_Interdisciplinary_Research._Theory_and_Practice

Lovely work! Thank you. I am also initially trained as a natural scientist, and now consider myself a ‘social-ecological researcher’ and have had to do a lot of learning about ontologies, epistemologies etc. I think I might use this paper as a discussion paper in our department as I think it is crucial for interdisciplinarians to understand these issues.

Kia ora Katie and Debbie, great post! I am a biophysical scientist who has come to social science and one of the struggles is being able to place the new and relevant concepts about questions that we don’t necessarily ask as biophysical scientists. Your table is a really useful aid to this – I immediately sent it to all my colleagues! It also makes it clearer to me how I can use the concept of triangulation that Bruce alluded to in his reply. So thank you for explaining so concisely. Thanks, Melissa

Hi Katie and Deborah,

Thank you for that discussion. I think that you have created a really useful table showing the philosophical continuums/polarities, how the various ontological and epistemological positions relate to each other, and the importance for researchers to be aware of them. In my own research practice, I am not committed to any one particular philosophical theory or perspective. They all appear to be true to some degree, that is, in some conceivable context – even though some of the concepts and philosophical positions appear, in the extreme form of their statement, to be contradictory, that is, if one end of a continuum/polarity is true then by implication it seems the other must be false – thus creating a quandary of research perspective. Hence the attraction, for me, of the application of a multiplicity of methods, approaches and philosophical perspectives – as and when they seem able to give ontological or epistemological insight – with triangulation between the results of the disparate approaches as the temporary arbiter of an evolving meaning and truth. This might be considered a pragmatic, perhaps even an opportunistic, approach to conducting science. However, as the old adage goes “the proof is in the pudding” – how useful is the knowledge obtained?

cheers Bruce

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed .

Discover more from Integration and Implementation Insights

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Type your email…

Continue reading

Kacper Grass 1 *

AM J QUALITATIVE RES, Volume 8, Issue 1, pp. 42-56

https://doi.org/10.29333/ajqr/14083

OPEN ACCESS   1513 Views   1726 Downloads

Download Full Text (PDF)

This essay reviews classic works on the philosophy of science and contemporary pedagogical guides to scientific inquiry in order to present a discussion of the three logics that underlie qualitative research in political science. The first logic, epistemology, relates to the essence of research as a scientific endeavor and is framed as a debate between positivist and interpretivist orientations within the discipline of political science. The second logic, ontology, relates to the approach that research takes to investigating the empirical world and is framed as a debate between positivist qualitative and quantitative orientations, which together constitute the vast majority of mainstream researchers within the discipline. The third logic, methodology, relates to the means by which research aspires to reach its scientific ends and is framed as a debate among positivist qualitative orientations. Additionally, the essay discusses the present state of qualitative research in the discipline of political science, reviews the various ways in which qualitative research is defined in the relevant literature, addresses the limitations and trade-offs that are inherently associated with the aforementioned logics of qualitative research, explores multimethod approaches to remedying these issues, and proposes avenues for acquiring further information on the topics discussed.

Keywords: qualitative research, epistemology, ontology, methodology

  • Baglione, L. A. (2020). Writing a research paper in political science: A practical guide to inquiry, structure, and methods . SAGE Publications.
  • Bates, R. H. (1993). Letter from the President: Area studies and the discipline. APSA-CP , 7 (1), 1–2. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1063-4584(05)80109-8
  • Brewer, J., & Hunter, A. (2006). Foundations of multimethod research: Synthesizing styles . SAGE Publications.
  • Brooks, S. M. (2013). The ethical treatment of human subjects and the institutional review board process. In L. Mosley (Ed.), Interview research in political science (pp. 45–66). Cornell University Press.
  • Caramani, D. (2020). Introduction to comparative politics. In D. Caramani (Ed.), Comparative politics (5th ed., pp. 1–18). Oxford University Press.
  • Collier, D. (1993). The comparative method. In A. Finifter (Ed.), Political science: The state of the discipline II (pp. 105–119). APSA.
  • Collier, D. (2008). Introduction. In G. Goertz (Ed.), Symposium: Case selection, case studies, and causal inference (pp. 2–4). American Political Science Association.
  • Fearon, J. D., & Laitin, D. D. (2008). Integrating qualitative and quantitative methods. In J. Box-Steffensmeier, H. E. Brady, & D. Collier (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of political methodology (pp. 756–776). Oxford University Press.
  • Freedman, D. (2008). Do the N’s justify the means? In G. Goertz (Ed.), Symposium: Case selection, case studies, and causal inference (pp. 4–6). American Political Science Association.
  • George, A. L., & Bennett, A. (2005). Case studies and theory development in the social sciences . Belfer Center for Science and International Affairs.
  • Gerring, J. (2008). Techniques for case selection: A response to David Freedman. In G. Goertz (Ed.), Symposium: Case selection, case studies, and causal inference (pp. 7–10). American Political Science Association.
  • Goertz, G. (2017). Multimethod research, causal mechanisms, and case studies: An integrated approach . Princeton University Press.
  • Goertz, G., & Mahoney, J. (2012). A tale of two cultures: Qualitative and quantitative research in the social sciences . Princeton University Press.
  • Hall, P. (2003). Aligning ontology and methodology. In J. Mahoney & D. Rueschemeyer (Eds.), Comparative historical analysis in the social sciences (pp. 373–404). Cambridge University Press.
  • Hanson, S. E. (2008). The contribution of area studies. In T. Landman & N. Robinson (Eds.), The SAGE Handbook of comparative politics (pp. 35–41). https://doi.org/10.4135/9780857021083.n10
  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science . Prentice-Hall.
  • Johnston, J. (1984). Econometric methods . McGraw-Hill.
  • Kapiszewski, D., Maclean, L. M., & Read, Benjamin, L. (2015). Field research in political science: practices and principles . Cambridge University Press.
  • Kaplan, A. (1998). The conduct of inquiry: Methodology for behavioural science . Routledge.
  • King, G. (1996). Why context should not count. Political Geography , 15 (2), 159–164. https://doi.org/10.1016/0962-6298(95)00079-8
  • King, G., Keohane, R. O., & Verba, S. (1994). Designing social inquiry: Scientific inference in qualitative research . Princeton University Press.
  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed.). University of Chicago Press.
  • Lane, R. (1996). Positivism, scientific realism and political science. Journal of Theoretical Politics , 8 (3), 361–382. https://doi.org/10.1177/0951692896008003003Lieberman, E. S. (2005). Nested analysis as a mixed-method strategy for comparative research. American Political Science Review , 99 (3), 435–452. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055405051762
  • Lukes, S. (2005). Power: A radical view . Red Globe Press.
  • Lustick, I. (1996). History, historiography, and political science: Multiple historical records and the problem of selection bias. The American Political Science Review , 90 (3), 605–618.
  • Lynch, J. F. (2013). Aligning sampling strategies with analytic goals. In L. Mosley (Ed.), Interview research in political science (pp. 31–44). Cornell University Press.
  • Mahoney, J. (2003). Strategies of causal assessment in comparative historical analysis. In J. Mahoney & D. Rueschemeyer (Eds.), Comparative historical analysis in the social sciences (pp. 337–372). Cambridge University Press.
  • Mahoney, J. (2007). Debating the state of comparative politics: Views from qualitative research. Comparative Political Studies , 40 (1), 32–38. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429026393-7
  • Mahoney, J., & Goertz, G. (2006). A tale of two cultures: Contrasting quantitative and qualitative research. Political Analysis , 14 (3), 227–249. https://doi.org/10.1093/pan/mpj017
  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive . John W. Parker.
  • Moore, B. (1966). The social origins of dictatorship and democracy: Lord and peasant in the making of the modern world (1st ed.). Penguin University Books.
  • Mosley, L. (2013a). Appendix: Sample materials for interview research. In L. Mosley (Ed.), Interview research in political science (pp. 245–269). Cornell University Press.
  • Mosley, L. (2013b). “Just talk to people?” Interviews in contemporary political science. In L. Mosley (Ed.), Interview research in political science (pp. 1–28). Cornell University Press.
  • Munck, G. L., & Snyder, R. (2007). Debating the direction of comparative politics: An analysis of leading journals. Comparative Political Studies , 40 (1), 5–31.
  • Nagel, E. (1979). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation . Hackett Publishing Company.
  • Pierson, P. (2003). Big, Slow-Moving, and...Invisible: Macrosocial processes in the study of comparative politics. In J. Mahoney & D. Rueschemeyer (Eds.), Comparative historical analysis in the social sciences (pp. 177–207). Cambridge University Press.
  • Popper, K. (1959/2002). The logic of scientific discovery . Routledge.
  • Przeworski, A., & Teune, H. (1970). The logic of comparative social inquiry: Comparative studies in behavioral science . Wiley-Interscience.
  • Ragin, C. (1987). The comparative method: Moving beyond qualitative and quantitative strategies . University of California Press.
  • Ragin, C. (2000). Fuzzy-set social science . University of Chicago Press.
  • Ragin, C. (2014). The comparative method: Moving beyond qualitative and quantitative strategies . University of California Press.
  • Rueschemeyer, D. (2003). Can one or a few cases yield theoretical gains? In J. Mahoney & D. Rueschemeyer (Eds.), Comparative historical analysis in the social sciences (pp. 305–336). Cambridge University Press.
  • Seawright, J. (2016). Better multimethod design: The promise of integrative multimethod research. Security Studies , 25 (1), 42–49. https://doi.org/10.1080/09636412.2016.1134187
  • Shively, W. P. (2013). The craft of political research . Pearson Education.
  • Shively, W. P., & Schultz, D. (2022). Power and Choice: An Introduction to Political Science (16th ed.). Roman and Littlefield.
  • Skocpol, T. (1979). States and Social Revolutions: A comparative analysis of France, Russia, and China . Cambridge University Press.
  • Small, M. L., & Calarco, J. M. (2022). Qualitative literacy: A guide to evaluating ethnographic and interview research . University of California Press.
  • Tarrow, S. (2004). Bridging the quantitative-qualitative divide. In H. E. Brady & D. Collier (Eds.), Rethinking social inquiry: Diverse tools, shared standards (pp. 171–180). Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Thies, C. G. (2002). A pragmatic guide to qualitative historical analysis in the study of international relations. International Studies Perspectives , 3 (4), 351–372. https://doi.org/10.1111/1528-3577.t01-1-00099
  • Trachtenberg, M. (2006). The craft of international history: A guide to method . Princeton University Press.
  • Van Evera, S. (1997). Guide to methods for students of political science . Cornell University Press.
  • Zurbano-Berenguer, B., Solá-Morales, S., & Marín-Conejo, S. (2021). Women facing violence: How women survivors assess news about gender violence. Cadernos Pagu , 2021 (63), 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1590/18094449202100630018

Ontology and Epistemology

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online: 13 January 2019
  • Cite this reference work entry

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  • John D. Hathcoat 2 ,
  • Cara Meixner 3 &
  • Mark C. Nicholas 4  

6627 Accesses

5 Citations

Health social science is an area of study wherein the methodological techniques used within the social sciences are applied to the investigation of human health. Methodological techniques, however, are not philosophically agnostic. Philosophical positions indeed matter in that they result in a range of individual and societal consequences. Consequently, it is important for students and researchers interested in studying the social aspects of health to understand the role of philosophical positions within research. Philosophical positions partly consist of ontological and epistemological assumptions. Ontological issues pertain to what exists, whereas epistemology focuses on the nature, limitations, and justification of human knowledge. This chapter introduces the reader to how ontological and epistemological positions are embedded within the biomedical, biopsychosocial, and critical alternative models of human functioning. Situating each of these models in relevant vignettes, we suggest that philosophical positions serve a dual role within inquiry in that they inform, and are in some circumstances informed by, the methodological and interpretative decisions enacted by researchers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

Towards a socially constructed and objective concept of mental disorder

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

Introduction. Why a Book on Naturalism in the Philosophy of Health?

Armstrong T. ADD/ADHD alternatives in the classroom. Alexandria: Association for Supervision and Curriculum Development; 1999.

Google Scholar  

Berkman LF, Kawachi I. A historical framework for social epidemiology. In: Berkman LF, Kawachi I, editors. Social epidemiology. New York: Oxford University Press; 2000. p. 3–12.

Biesta G. Pragmatism and the philosophical foundations of mixed methods research. In: Taskakkori A, Teddlie C, editors. Handbook of mixed methods in social and behavioral research. 2nd ed. Thousand Oaks: Sage; 2010. p. 95–118.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Bothwell LE, Podolsky SH. The emergence of the randomized, controlled trial. N Engl J Med. 2016;375(6):501–4.

Article   Google Scholar  

Creswell JW. Mapping the field of mixed methods research. J Mixed Methods Res. 2009;3(2):95–108.

Creswell JW, PlanoClark VL. Designing and conducting mixed methods approaches. Thousand Oaks: Sage; 2011.

Crotty M. The foundations of social research: meaning and perspective in the research process. Thousand Oaks: Sage; 1998.

Denzin NK, Lincoln YS, editors. The Sage handbook of qualitative research. Thousand Oaks: Sage; 2011.

Engel GL. The need for a new medical model: a challenge for biomedicine. Science. 1977;196:129–36.

Englehardt TH Jr. The disease of masturbation: values and the concept of disease. Bull Hist Med. 1974;48(2):234–48.

Fleck L. Genesis and development of a scientific fact. In: Trenn T, Merton RK, editors (F. Bradley & T. Trenn, Trans.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; 1935/1979.

Foucault M. Madness and civilization: a history of insanity in the age of reason (R. Howard, Trans.). New York: Routledge; 1961/1989.

Freire P. Pedagogy of the oppressed (M.B. Ramos, Trans.). New York: Bloomsbury Academic; 1970/2014.

Gale JE, Dolbin-MacNab ML. Qualitative research for family therapy. In: Mille RB, Johnson LN, editors. Advanced methods in family therapy research: a focus on validity and change. New York: Routledge; 2014. p. 247–65.

Greene JC. Mixed methods in social inquiry. San Francisco: Wiley; 2007.

Guba E, Lincoln Y. Competing paradigms in qualitative research. In: Denzin N, Lincoln Y, editors. Handbook of qualitative research. Thousand Oaks: Sage; 1994. p. 105–17.

Guba EG, Lincoln YS Paradigmatic Controversies, Contradictions, and Emerging Confluences. In: Denzin NK, Lincoln YS, editors. The Sage handbook of qualitative research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications; 2005. pp. 191–215.

Hathcoat JD, Meixner C. Pragmatism, factor analysis, and the conditional incompatibility thesis in mixed methods research. J Mixed Methods Res. 2017;11(4):433–49.

Hathcoat JD, Nicholas M. Epistemology. In: Coghlan D, Brydon-Miller M, editors. The SAGE encyclopedia of action research (“E” entries, pp. 285–332). Washington, DC: Sage; 2014.

Hausman DM. Health and well-being. In: Solomon M, Simon JR, Kincaid H, editors. The Routledge companion to philosophy of medicine. New York: Routledge; 2017. p. 27–35.

Heidegger M. Being and time (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). New York: State University of New York Press; 1953/1996.

Hoffman B. Disease, illness, and sickness. In: Solomon M, Simon JR, Kincaid H, editors. The Routledge companion to philosophy of medicine. New York: Routledge; 2017. p. 16–26.

Hood SB. Psychological measurement and methodological realism. Erkenntnis. 2013;78:739–61.

Houghton C, Hunter A, Meskell P. Linking aims, paradigm and method in nursing research. Nurs Res. 2012;20(2):34–9.

Howe KR. Against the quantitative-qualitative incompatibility thesis or dogmas die hard. Educational researcher. 1988;17(8):10–16.

Hsu JL. A brief history of vaccines: smallpox to the present. S D Med. 2013;33(7):3–37.

Lovett BJ, Hood, SB. Comorbidity in child psychiatric diagnosis: Conceptual complications. In Perring C, Wells LA, editors. Diagnostic dilemmas in child and adolescent psychiatry: Philosophical perspectives. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 2014. p. 80–97.

Illich I. Medicine is a major threat to health. An interview by Sam Keen. Psychol Today. 1976;9(12):66–67.

Koenig HG. Religion and medicine: historical background and reasons for separation. Int J Psychiatry Med. 2000;30(4):385–98.

Kuhn T. The structure of scientific revolutions. 4th ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; 1962/2012.

Ladyman J. Understanding philosophy of science. New York: Routledge; 2002.

Book   Google Scholar  

Lincoln Y, Guba E. Naturalistic inquiry. Newbury Park: Sage; 1985.

Longino CF. The limits of scientific medicine. J Health Soc Policy. 1998;9(4):101–16.

Lovett BJ, Hood SB. Realism and operationism in psychiatric diagnosis. Philos Psychol. 2011;24(2):207–22.

Low G. Thomas Sydenham: the English Hippocrates. Aust N Z J Surg. 1999;69:258–62.

Maxwell JA. Causal explanation, qualitative research, and scientific inquiry in education. Educ Res. 2004;33(2):3–11.

Moon K, Blackman D. A guide to understanding social science research for natural scientists. Conserv Biol. 2014;28(5):1167–77.

Morgan DL. Paradigms lost and pragmatism regained: methodological implications of combining quantitative and qualitative methods. J Mixed Methods Res. 2007;1(1):48–76.

Murray M. Social history of health psychology: context and textbooks. Health Psychol Rev. 2014;8(2):215–37.

Nicholas M, Hathcoat JD. Ontology. In: Coghlan D, Brydon-Miller M, editors. The SAGE encyclopedia of action research (“O” entries, pp. 285–332). Washington, DC: Sage; 2014.

Onwuegbuzie AJ, Johnson RB, Collins KMT. Call for mixed methods analysis: a philosophical framework for combining qualitative and quantitative approaches. Int J Mult Res Approaches. 2009;3:114–39.

Phillips DC. Philosophy, science, and social inquiry: contemporary methodological controversies in social science and related applied fields of research. Oxford: Pergamon; 1987.

Poli R. Ontology: the categorical stance. In: Poli R, Seibt J, editors. Theory and application of ontology: philosophical perspectives. New York: Springer; 2010. p. 1–22.

Quine WVO. Two dogmas of empiricism. In: Quine WVO, editor. From a logical point of view. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1953. p. 20–46.

Robinson OC. The idiographic/nomothetic dichotomy: tracing historical origins of contemporary confusions. Hist Philos Psychol. 2011;13(2):32–9.

Sandelowski M. Unmixed mixed-methods research. Res Nurs Health. 2014;37:3–8.

Sisti D, Caplan AL. The concept of disease. In: Solomon M, Simon JR, Kincaid H, editors. The Routledge companion to philosophy of medicine. New York: Routledge; 2017. p. 5–15.

Smith R. In search of “non-disease”. Br Med J. 2002;324:883–5.

Smith KA. Louis Pasteur, the father of immunology? Front Immunol. 2012;3:1–10.

Suhrs J, Hammers D, Dobbins-Buckland K, Zimak E, Hughes CH. The relationship of malingering test failure to self-reported symptoms and neuropsychological findings in adults referred for ADHD evaluation. Arch Clin Neuropsychol. 2008;23:521–30.

Suls J, Rothman A. Evolution of the biopsychosocial model: prospects and challenges for health psychology. Health Psychol. 2004;23:119–25.

Sydeman T. Observationes Medicae circa Morgorum Acutorum Historiam et Curationem. London: Kettilby; 1676. As cited in Low G. Thomas Sydenham: the English Hippocrates. Aust N Z J Surg. 1999;69:258–62.

Valtorta NK, Kanaan M, Gilbody S, Ronzi S, Hanratty B. Loneliness and social isolation as risk factors for coronary heart disease and stroke: systematic review and meta-analysis of longitudinal observational studies. Heart. 2016;102(13):1009–16.

Veatch RM. How philosophy of medicine has changed medical ethics. J Med Philos. 2006;31(6):585–600.

Wade DT, Halligan PW. The biopsychosocial model of illness: a model whose time has come. Clin Rehabil. 2017;31(8):995–1004.

Weaver K, Olson JK. Understanding paradigms used for nursing research. J Adv Nurs. 2006;53(4):459–69.

White K, Willis E. Positivism resurgent: the epistemological foundations of evidence-based medicine. Health Sociol Rev. 2002;11:5–15.

Whitley R. Global mental health: concepts, conflicts, and controversies. Epidemiol Psychiatr Sci. 2015;24(4):285–91.

Williams MJ. Problems of knowledge: a critical introduction to epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press; 2001.

World Health Organization. Basic documents (48th ed.). Italy: World Health Organization; 1948/2014.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Graduate Psychology, Center for Assessment and Research Studies, James Madison University, Harrisonburg, VA, USA

John D. Hathcoat

Department of Graduate Psychology, Center for Faculty Innovation, James Madison University, Harrisonburg, VA, USA

Cara Meixner

Framingham State University, Framingham, MA, USA

Mark C. Nicholas

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John D. Hathcoat .

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

School of Science and Health, Western Sydney University, Penrith, NSW, Australia

Pranee Liamputtong

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this entry

Cite this entry.

Hathcoat, J.D., Meixner, C., Nicholas, M.C. (2019). Ontology and Epistemology. In: Liamputtong, P. (eds) Handbook of Research Methods in Health Social Sciences. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-5251-4_56

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-5251-4_56

Published : 13 January 2019

Publisher Name : Springer, Singapore

Print ISBN : 978-981-10-5250-7

Online ISBN : 978-981-10-5251-4

eBook Packages : Social Sciences Reference Module Humanities and Social Sciences Reference Module Business, Economics and Social Sciences

Share this entry

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Logo for OPEN OKSTATE

Interpretivism

Often contrasted with Positivism is Interpretivism. The starting point for Interpretivism – which is sometimes called Anti-Positivism – is that knowledge in the human and social sciences cannot conform to the model of natural science because there are features of human experience that cannot objectively be “known”. This might include emotions; understandings; values; feelings; subjectivities; socio-cultural factors; historical influence; and other meaningful aspects of human being. Instead of finding “truth” the Interpretivist aims to generate understanding and often adopts a relativist position.

Qualitative methods are preferred as ways to investigate these phenomena. Data collected might be unstructured (or “messy”) and correspondingly a range of techniques for approaching data collection have been developed. Interpretivism acknowledges that it is impossible to remove cultural and individual influence from research, often instead making a virtue of the positionality of the researcher and the socio-cultural context of a study.

One key consideration here is the purported validity of qualitative research. Interpretivism tends to emphasize the subjective over the objective. If the starting point for an investigation is that we can’t fully and objectively know the world, how can we do research into this without everything being a matter of opinion? Essentially Positivism and Interpretivism retain different ontologies and epistemologies with contrasting notions of rigour and validity (in the broadest rather than statistical sense). Interpretivist research often embraces a relativist epistemology, bringing together different perspectives in search of an overall understanding or narrative.

Kivunja & Kuyini (2017) describe the essential features of Interpretivism as:

  • The admission that the social world cannot be understood from the standpoint of an individual
  • The belief that realities are multiple and socially constructed
  • The acceptance that there is inevitable interaction between the researcher and his or her research participants
  • The acceptance that context is vital for knowledge and knowing.
  • The belief that knowledge is created by the findings, can be value laden and the values need to be made explicit
  • The need to understand the individual rather than universal laws
  • The belief that causes and effects are mutually interdependent
  • The belief that contextual factors need to be taken into consideration in any systematic pursuit of understanding

Interpretivism as a research paradigm is often accompanied by Constructivism as an ontological and epistemological grounding. Many learning theories emphasize Constructivism as an organising principle, and Constructivism often underlies aspects of educational research.

Interpretivist Methods : Case Studies; Conversational analysis; Delphi; Description; Document analysis; Interviews; Focus Groups; Grounded theory; Phenomenography; Phenomenology; Thematic analysis

[INSERT Figure 2]

methodological aspects of Positivism and Interpretivism. Positivism Interpretivism Ontology Being in the world Direct access (Naturalism) Indirect access (Idealism) Reality Objective, accessible Subjectively experienced Epistemology Relation between knowledge and reality Objective knowledge of the world is possible supported by appropriate method Objective knowledge of the world is possible supported by appropriate method Epistemological goals Generalisation, abstraction, discovery of law-like relationships Knowledge of specific, concrete cases and examples Basic approach Hypothesis formation and testing Describing and seeking to understand phenomena in context Methodology Focus Description and explanation Understanding and interpretation Research Perspective Detached, objective Embedded in the phenomena under investigation Role of emotions Strict separation between the cognitions and feeling of the researchers Emotional response can be part of coming to understanding Limits of researcher influence Discovery of external, objective reality – minimal influence Object of study is potentially influenced by the activity of the researcher Valued approaches Consistency, clarity, reproducibility, rationality, lack of bias Insight, appreciation of context and prior understanding Fact/value distinction Clear distinction between facts and values Distinction is less rigid, acknowledges entanglement Archetypal research methods Quantitative (e.g. statistical analysis) Qualitative (e.g. case study) Figure 2. Ontology, Epistemology and Methodology across Positivism and Interpretivism (adapted from Carson et al., 2001)

Research Methods Handbook Copyright © 2020 by Rob Farrow; Francisco Iniesto; Martin Weller; and Rebecca Pitt is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License , except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book

Chamila Wijethissa

  • University of Kelaniya

Can someone explain the ontology and epistemology in simple way?

Most recent answer.

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

Popular answers (1)

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

Top contributors to discussions in this field

Jamel Chahed

  • University of Tunis El Manar

Karl Pfeifer

  • University of Saskatchewan

H.G. Callaway

  • Temple University

Michael Bergin

  • South East Technological University

David L Morgan

  • Portland State University

Get help with your research

Join ResearchGate to ask questions, get input, and advance your work.

All Answers (202)

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  • Philosophical Foundations 1.pptx 75.3 kB

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  • Ontological Hierarc hy.JPG 86 kB

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  • Ontology sounds like ‘on toe logy’, or the study of what you just dropped on your toe . Now, if you just dropped a hammer on your toe, I guarantee you’re going to be thinking about reality. You’re going to be thinking about real hammers and real pain, in the real world. There’s no way you’re going to be in the mind-frame to ask: “How do I produce knowledge about this hammer?” You’ll be pretty focused on its reality. That’s ontology.
  • Epistemology sounds a bit like ‘epic stem ology’, or the study of epic stems . Imagine your mate, who is a plant scientist, comes up to you and says: “Hey buddy, look at the epic stem on this plant, how cool”. I’m guessing your first reaction will be: Is that really an epic stem? How does Dave know that’s an epic stem? Why does Dave have some right weird opinions? You can see these are all questions about knowledge, ie epistemology.

qualitative research ontology and epistemology

Similar questions and discussions

  • Asked 6 May 2014

Shanthi Thomas

  • Asked 23 July 2015

Chaudry Bilal Ahmad Khan

  • Asked 29 September 2019

Leyli Cillien

  • Asked 30 August 2023

Raphael Neelamkavil

  • Asked 23 January 2014

Ilona Box

  • Asked 25 February 2020

Jake D. Franklin

  • Asked 17 August 2023

Britt Anne O'Keefe

  • Asked 21 September 2022
  • Asked 3 October 2021

R M M Pradeep

Related Publications

Youngchul Kim

  • Recruit researchers
  • Join for free
  • Login Email Tip: Most researchers use their institutional email address as their ResearchGate login Password Forgot password? Keep me logged in Log in or Continue with Google Welcome back! Please log in. Email · Hint Tip: Most researchers use their institutional email address as their ResearchGate login Password Forgot password? Keep me logged in Log in or Continue with Google No account? Sign up

IMAGES

  1. Ontology and epistemology: An explainer

    qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  2. The Ontology and Epistemology of Qualitative Research

    qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  3. What is the relationship among Ontology, Epistemology, Methodology and Method

    qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  4. Ontology and Epistemology Diagram

    qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  5. Ontology, Epistemology and Methodology

    qualitative research ontology and epistemology

  6. Ontology vs Epistemology

    qualitative research ontology and epistemology

COMMENTS

  1. A guide to ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives for

    Social science research guide consisting of ontology, epistemology, and philosophical perspectives. When read from left to right, elements take on a more multidimensional nature (eg., epistemology: objectivism to subjectivism). ... Pingback: Week 2 - Ontology and Epistemology - Research Methods. Jules André-Brown. January 28, 2020 at 10:15 ...

  2. Linking Ontology, Epistemology and Research Methodology

    This paper outlines the. links among ontology, epistemology and research methodology by exploring. ontological, epistemological and methodological perspectives in the research. It discusses how ...

  3. Epistemology-Ontology Relations in Social Research: A Review

    New Delhi: Primus Books, 2017, 485 pp., ₹ 1,395 (hardback). ISBN: 978-93-84082-05-5. Ananta Kumar Giri (Ed.), Cultivating Pathways of Creative Research: New Horizons of Transformative Practice and collaborative Imagination.

  4. Perspectives on the epistemological bases for qualitative research

    This chapter reviews and clarifies the various ways in which qualitative researchers approach the creation of knowledge. Qualitative research can take many forms. Within the general rubric of qualitative research, we can find a wide range of activities that are driven by different goals, deploy different research strategies, and generate different kinds of insights.

  5. PDF Epistemologies and Methodologies in Qualitative Research

    Definitions: Methodology. Methodology: justifies the methods. A theory and analysis of how research should proceed. Analysis of the assumptions, principles and procedures in a particular approach to an inquiry. A description, explanation and the justification of the methods used. Methodology connects research to theory and discipline.

  6. Full article: Philosophical Paradigms in Qualitative Research Methods

    Similar recommendations are found in Wagner et al.'s systematic review, which identified several studies that recommended that "students should be exposed to philosophy of science and epistemological debates related to qualitative research" (Citation 2019, p. 12), and that "paradigms linked to qualitative research be introduced in the first year and sustained throughout a curriculum ...

  7. PDF Epistemological Dimensions in Qualitative Research: the Construction of

    Objectivism. Meaning and meaningful reality exists as such apart from the operation of any consciousness. In this epistemology, of what it means to know, understanding and values are considered objectified in the people researchers study. Using appropriate methods researchers can discover objective truth.

  8. Demystifying Ontology and Epistemology in Research Methods

    ontology and epistemology mean, what their variants are and how they relate to research. Ontology. Ontology is the study of 'being' and is concerned with 'what is', i.e., the nature of ...

  9. Ontology, Epistemology, and Methodology: A Clarification

    Story as link between nursing practice, ontology, epistemology. Image, 23 (4), 245-248. Google Scholar. Cash, K. (1997). Social epistemology, gender and nursing theory. International Journal of Nursing ... Toward Greater Clarity in Generic Qualitative Research. ... Epistemology and Metaphysics for Qualitative Research. 2016. SAGE Knowledge ...

  10. Qualitative and Quantitative Methodologies Compared: Ontological and

    and qualitative approaches lies in the issue of ontology and epistemology (Guba, 1987). Downloaded by [Oklahoma State University] at 01:04 24 June 2014 ... Qualitative research: Advancing the ...

  11. The Three Logics of Qualitative Research: Epistemology, Ontology, and

    This essay reviews classic works on the philosophy of science and contemporary pedagogical guides to scientific inquiry in order to present a discussion of the three logics that underlie qualitative research in political science. The first logic, epistemology, relates to the essence of research as a scientific endeavor and is framed as a debate between positivist and interpretivist ...

  12. Sage Research Methods Video: Qualitative and Mixed Methods

    Sage Research Methods Video: Qualitative and Mixed Methods - Ontology and Epistemology. This visualization demonstrates how methods are related and connects users to relevant content. Find step-by-step guidance to complete your research project. Answer a handful of multiple-choice questions to see which statistical method is best for your data.

  13. Epistemology and Metaphysics for Qualitative Research

    • Empiricism • Rationalism • Realism • Skepticism • Idealism • Positivism • Post-positivism • Idea-ism • Hermeneutics • Phenomenology • Social Ontology • Quantum Mechanics Essential reading for new and experienced researchers, this 'must' for any social science bookshelf will help unlock a new level of research ...

  14. Ontology and Epistemology

    Positions taken toward the nature of reality, or an object of investigation, are ontological, whereas stances toward the meaning and process of obtaining knowledge reflect what is epistemological. Together, ontological and epistemological positions, even when tacit, richly inform the arc of research in the health social sciences.

  15. International Journal of Qualitative Methods Comparisons of Adaptations

    The most widely used qualitative research methodologies are grounded theory and phenomenology. Both methodologies have ... ontology but has a different epistemology rooted from social constructivism (where reality is socially co-constructed by the researcher and participants) that is interchangeably used with

  16. PDF An Invitation to Qualitative Research

    Ontology: An ontology is a philosophical belief system about the nature of social reality—what can be known and how. The conscious and unconscious questions, assumptions, and beliefs that the researcher brings to the research endeavor serve as the initial basis for an ontological position.

  17. Qualitative and Quantitative Methodologies Compared: Ontological and

    This article clarifies fundamental differences between qualitative and quantitative methodologies from ontological and epistemological perspectives. Additionally, it explicates the issue of compatibility and integration of the two approaches.

  18. PDF Qualitative Research: A Decisive Element to Epistemological

    itative research in social science is an invaluable way to understand social world. Core objective(s) of qualitative resear. hers are concerned with how to study or learn about the nature of the social world. The process of st. dying, knowing or learning about social world generates some philosophical debates. Before discussing about the issues ...

  19. Theory and application of research principles and philosophical

    Coherent research requires synthesis of ontology, epistemology and methodology with the choice of research design based on the most appropriate approach. Qualitative research has greatly enhanced its reputation for methodological rigour and the uptake of IPA is increasing within health and social care.

  20. Interpretivism

    epistemology, bringing together different perspectives in search of an overall understanding or narrative. Kivunja & Kuyini (2017) describe the essential features of Interpretivism as: The admission that the social world cannot be understood from the standpoint of an individual. The belief that realities are multiple and socially constructed.

  21. (Pdf) the Ontological and Epistemological Foundations of Qualitative

    qualitative methods, rarely do they dig out issues of epistemology and ontology. Researchers in their technical and theo retical debates have given little attention to the qualitative approach ...

  22. Ontology, Epistemology and Axiology in Quantitative and Qualitative

    In conclusion effort was made to clarify what ontology, epistemology and axiology entail so as to have clear understanding of what the terms mean. Positioning Research Paradigm, (Sexton, 2003) No ...

  23. The Judgment of the Nations: Structural Sin, Social Ontology, and

    This paper argues that we can accommodate the worries of the first group with the more robust social ontology implied by the second. This social ontology can be found both in the work of contemporary analytic philosophers and, inchoately at least, in traditional Aristotelianism, and it allows us to give a more precise account of the metaphysics ...

  24. Can someone explain the ontology and epistemology in simple way?

    Ontology is one's conception of reality---the world that we live in; Epistemology is our idea of the knowledge which we can glean from our conception of reality. Simple---or as complex as one ...